Introduction
What Is Enlightenment?
I
in 1794 marie-jean-antoine-Nicolas de Caritat, Marquis de Condorcet, sat in hiding in a tiny room in the house of Madame Vernet in the rue Servandoni in Paris. By the light of a candle, shaded so as not to reveal his whereabouts while the forces of the French Revolution closed in on him, he wrote a brief fragment of what was intended to be a much longer work, the Sketch for a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind. Condorcet was one of the great mathematicians of his or any other age, one of the creators of differential calculus, and the first person to attempt to predict the possible outcome of human decision-making by using mathematics, which makes him the forefather of modern political science. He was also a champion of equal rights for women and for all peoples of all races and an abolitionist who devised the worldâs first state education system. Like all men of his class in the eighteenth century, he was deeply involved in politics.1 He had been an active supporter of the Revolution in its early stages, becoming the Paris representative of the National Assembly in 1791 and then its secretary. Although a member of the Girodins, the more moderate of the two revolutionary parties, he continued until his death to see the Revolution as a force that had accelerated the normal course of history, and he looked upon the French constitution, as did its authors, as not merely a constitution for a new republican France but a constitution for humankind.2 When, in December 1792, the National Assembly put the king, Louis XVI, on trial as a traitor, Condorcet supported the move, believing, like the Anglo-American radical Tom Paineânow a naturalized French citizenâthat it would show the world that kings, too, could be held accountable for their crimes. But because, like all good liberalsâlike Paine, indeedâhe rejected the idea that the state had the right to take human life, he passionately opposed the idea of his execution. This did not win him friends among the revolutionary hard-liners, and when in 1793 he voted against the new constitution proposed by the Jacobins, he was branded as a traitor and an enemy of the Revolution. A warrant for his arrest was issued on July 8, after which he went into hiding in the rue Servandoni. On March 25, 1794, sensing that the forces of the Terror were closing in on him and fearful that his continuing presence might prove dangerous to the good Madame Vernet, he fled Paris, taking with him only a volume of the poems of Horace. He seems to have spent the night of the 26th in the countryside around Clamart, some nine kilometers outside Paris, and on the 27th, exhausted, famished, and apparently wounded in one leg, he stopped at an inn and ordered an omelette. The innkeeper asked him how many eggs he wanted. âTwelve,â replied Condorcet. He was immediately arrested and taken to Bourg-la Reine to await prosecution by the dreaded Revolutionary Tribunal. (Only aristocrats ever ate so many eggs at one sitting.)3 Two days later, on March 29, 1794, he died in prison, under somewhat mysterious circumstances, the victim of what the conservative Anglo-Irish orator, philosopher, and political theorist Edmund Burke nicely called âthe delusive plausibilities of moral politicians.â4
Condorcet was one of the most prominent, distinguished, and widely loved victims of the revolutionary fury, yet for the enemies of the Enlightenment, on both the extreme left and the far right, he became one of the worst exponents of the confidence in human rationality that had supposedly made the Revolution possible. âThat philosophe so dear to the Revolution,â the arch-conservative Joseph de Maistre said of him, âwho used his life to prepare the unhappiness of the present generation, graciously willing perfection to posterity.â5 Maximilien de Robespierre, the sanguineous theoretician of the Terror, thought no better of him. âA great geometrician,â he called him after his death, âor so say the men of letters; a great man of letters in the opinion of the geometricians, and later a timid conspirator despised by all parties.â6
Much of this hostility, and De Maistreâs in particular, was not directed at Condorcetâs mathematical writings, although his vision of a life regulated by the certainty of predication struck someâas it did the Romantic literary critic Charles-Augustin Sainte-Beuveâas a recipe for âuniversal mediocrity,â in which there would be no place âfor great virtues, for acts of heroism,â a bright new world whose unfortunate citizens would all die of boredom. It was directed instead at the Sketch, which was his most accessible and would become his best-known work.7
As its somewhat provisional title makes clear, the Sketch is a universal history of mankind, divided into ten âepochs.â It starts in prehistory with small wandering bands whose condition can only be inferred by âexamining the intellectual and moral faculties and the physical constitution of man.â It then takes the reader through the successive stages of human social evolution until it arrives at the current condition of the âenlightened nations of Europe.â The final epoch lies in the future. It is here that all the promises of that period, which, like his contemporaries, Condorcet referred to as the âcentury of lightâ or the âcentury of philosophyâ and we today call the Enlightenment, âwould finally be realized.â The natural sciences, he argued, which had achieved such astounding successes in the seventeenth century, are based upon one single and unwavering belief: that all the laws of the universe are ânecessary and constantâ throughout time. As humans are part of this universe, the study of their history, although it is unlikely to uncover laws as certain as those of physics, will at least allow the historian to âpredict with great probability the events of the future.â What, then, will the future bring? Given the conditions in which he was writing, Condorcet was perhaps being unduly optimistic. But he remained convinced that
Our hopes for the future state of the human species may be summed up in three important points: the elimination of the inequality between nations; progress in equality within the same peoples; and finally the real perfection of mankind. All peoples should one day approach the state of civilization attained by the most enlightened, the most free, and the most free from prejudices, such as are the French and the Anglo-Americans.
Today we have grown wary of the word civilization, after the uses to which, in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, it was put. But Condorcet understood it not as some undifferentiated cultural and political state that all peoples should be compelled to adopt but what he called an âequal diffusion of enlightenment,â a condition in which all mankind would acquire
the necessary enlightenment to conduct themselves in accordance with their own reason in the common affairs of life, and to maintain them, free of prejudices, so that they might know their rights and be at liberty to exercise them according to their own opinion and their conscience, where all might, through the development of their faculties, obtain the certain means to provide for their needs.
In 1794 these conditions clearly did not yet exist. But Condorcet assured his readers that the âprogress which science and civilizationâ had made was such that there was âthe strongest reasons to believe that nature has set no limit to our hopes.â Even now, or so he thought, the principles behind the French constitution were shared by all enlightened beings across the world. Soon they would be shared by all mankind. Soon, what he called the âgreat religions of the Orientââby which he meant not only Islam but also, and most especially, Christianityâwhich for so long had kept their cringing adherents trapped in a state of âslavery without hope and a perpetual infancy,â would finally be revealed for the lies, tricks, and deceits that they were. When that day arrived, âThe sun will rise only upon a world of free men who will recognize no master other than their own reason, where tyrants and slaves, priests and their stupid or hypocritical instruments, will exist only in history or in the theatre.â When that day arrived, as he had told the doubtless skeptical members of the AcadĂ©mie française twelve years earlier, âWe will have seen reason emerge victorious from that struggle, so long and so painful, [so] that at last we will be able to write: truth has triumphed; the human race is saved!â8
Some aspects of Condorcetâs imaginary future can today sound uncomfortably like a precursor to the objectives of the civilizing missions that would flood so much of the world in the nineteenth century. Yet for all his belief in the goods that the inescapable forward march of western civilization would finally bring, he was also acutely aware of the depredations that that civilization, in its insatiable quest for âsugar and spicesâ in Africa, Asia, and America, and âour betrayals, our bloody contempt for men of a different color or belief, our insolence and our usurpationsâ had inflicted on âthose vast lands.â9 But he firmly believed that now that the perpetrators themselves had thrown off the kings and priests who had been largely responsible for these horrors, these depredations would soon be only a distant memory, and the peoples of Africa and Asia (alas, it was already too late for the poor American Indians) would be waiting patiently for the day when they might become the âfriends and disciplesâ of new, enlightened Europeans.
Condorcetâs vision of the future, although challenged and derided, has had and continues to have a powerful hold over the imagination of the western world. It is, although he does not use the term, deeply cosmopolitan. Cosmopolitanism, like so much else in the western philosophical tradition, has been with us since antiquity. Diogenes the Cynic of the fourth century bce, the man famous for living in barrel and walking the streets of Athens at midday with a lighted lamp in search of an âhonest man,â was supposedly the first to declare, when asked from what city (polis) he came: âI am a citizen of the world [kosmo-polites].â10 Later the expression was taken up by the Stoics, who, as we shall see, were to play a transformative role in its subsequent history. For all the opprobrium directed against it in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, when âcosmopolitanismâ came to be cast as a form of immorality, a betrayal of every manâs true and proper objects of loyalty, which was not to the world but to the nation, it has shown itself to be remarkably resilient. It has been the inspiration behind the League of Nations and the United Nations, behind the International Court of Justice and the beleaguered, but still enduring, belief in the possibility for a truly international law. Today it provides the theoretical foundations for the modern conceptions of âinternational justice,â âgeo-governance,â âglobal civil society,â and âConstitutional patriotism.â11 It has, as the Anglo-Ghanaian philosopher Kwame Anthony Appiah, himself an exemplary cosmopolitan, rightly says of it, âcertainly proved a survivor.â12
The version of cosmopolitanism that Condorcet was proposing, like Condorcet himself, was also unmistakably a creature of âthe Enlightenment.â To say that, however, is to beg a number of questions. For just what exactly the Enlightenment was has been the subject of irate and furious debates ever since the eighteenth century itself. No other intellectual movement, no other period in history, has attracted so much disagreement, so much intransigence, so much simple anger. The key terms of almost every modern conflict over how we are to define and understand âhumanityââmodernism, postmodernism, universalism, imperialism, multiculturalismâultimately refer back to some understanding of the Enlightenment. No topic of historical debate, none of the great controversies over the turning points in history or over the moment in which âmodernityâ is believed to have begunânot the Renaissance, nor the Reformation, not the Scientific Revolution nor the Industrial Revolutionâhas exercised anything like the hold that the Enlightenment does over the ideological divisions within the modern world.
The struggle over the identity of the Enlightenment was also a part of the Enlightenment itself. In December 1783 the Berlinische MonatsÂschrift, a widely read and generally progressive journal, published an article by a theologian and educational reformer named Johann Friedrich Zöllner. The article was on the desirability of purely civil marriagesâa somewhat recondite topic. It might have passed unnoticed, and probably unread, if it had not been for a single footnote. âWhat is enlightenment?â Zöllner asked. âThis question, which is almost as important as what is truth, should indeed be answered before one begins enlightening. And still I have never found it answered!â13 It was perhaps the most significant footnote in the entire history of western thoughtâit was certainly the most widely discussed. Six years later, shortly before the outbreak of the French Revolution, the German poet and philosopher Christoph Martin Wielandâonce described as the German Voltaireâwhile seated on the toilet and reaching for what he coyly calls a âmaculatureâ (in other words, a piece of toilet paper), found, ânot without a slight shudder of astonishment,â that the sheet of âgood white soft paperâ he held in his hand had printed on it six questions, the first of which was: âWhat is enlightenment?â14
The debate that Zöllner had inadvertently begun seems to have been a uniquely German event. But the widespread diffusion of the term EnlightenmentâAufklĂ€rung in German, LumiĂšres in French, IlustraciĂłn in Spanish, Illuminismo in Italian, Oplysning in Danishâand the confusion it aroused was by no means confined to the German-speaking lands (there was, as yet, no such place as Germany). In France, in England, in Spain, in Sweden, in Holland, in Italy, in Portugal people had been asking themselves similar questions since at least the middle of the century. Despite this, however, the answer was very far from being, as Wieland breezily claimed, âknown to everyone.â Condorcet himself, who was not beset by the intellectual anxiety that has afflicted modern historians, described it as a âdisposition of minds.â The Germans called it a Denkart, a frame of mind, and the French a mentalitĂ©, a view on the world. The great Jewish philosopher Moses Mendelssohn took it to be the theoretical part of education (culture being the âobjectiveâ part).15 For the sometime Jesuit novice and Freemason Karl Leonhard Reinhold, it was the process of âmaking . . . rational men out of men who are capable of rationality.â16 For the Prussian jurist Ernst Ferdinand Klein it meant, rather more prosaically, the freedom of the press (something he seems to imagine, wistfully, that the Prussian king Frederick the Great had endorsed). For the radical and theologian Carl Friedrich Bahrdt it meant the âholiest, most important, most inviolable right of man,â to âthink for oneself.â17 It was a âpure insight,â in the words of the nineteenth-century German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, that seeped into menâs thoughts like a âperfumeâ orâsince Hegel was at best uncertain about its benefitsâan âinfection.â18 It may well be true, as the twentieth-century German philosopher (and author of what is still one of the most powerfully persuasive accounts of the Enlightenment) Ernst Cassirer said in 1932, that âthe real philosophy of the Enlightenment is not simply the sum total of what its leading thinkers . . . [t]hought and taught,â but a process, the âpulsation of the inner intellectual life,â that consisted âless in the certain individual doctrines than in the form and manner of intellectual activity in general.â19 Whatever it was, it was certainly ubiquitous. Even a Scottish cleric on one of the remotest islands in Europe could protest to the urbane lowlander James Boswell that up there in ultima Thule he and his companions were âmore enlightenedâ than Boswell might have supposed.20
Yet for all the questioning, and for all the massive historical industry that has grown up around the Enlightenment, we are still far from certain quite what all this means. What exactly was Wielandâs light? What was its source? Are we talking about a philosophical project or a social movementâor a combination of both, or neither? Then there is a somewhat different question. Even if there were people throughout Europe (even in Scotland) who were proud to call themselves âenlightened,â even if these people were conscious of living through something that might be called âthe century of enlightenmentâ or of philosophy, even if they believed that it was a distinct and probably transformative moment in western history, did these termsâenlightenment, philosophy, and so onâmean the same thing to everyone everywhere? A number of historians have argued that, on close examination, there was so very little in common among, say, British or German philosophers, French philosophes, Italian historians, and Spanish political economists, beyond a dislike of bigotry and a certain conviviality, that it makes no real sense to talk about the Enlightenment. Instead we should, as the historian J.G.A. Pocock has insisted, abandon the definite article altogether and instead talk only about âEnlightenments.â21
It is certainly true that there were some very significant differences among what the enlightened in France, the German-speaking states, or Britain, not to mention in Spain, Portugal, Naples, Milan, Denmark, and Ireland, thought on almost every topic. The intellectual, moral, and affective hold over even the most independent minds of traditions, institutions, religions, and customs obviously varied immensely across Europe. The Italians, the Spanish, and the Portuguese were more cautious about what they said about established religion and monarchical government than either the French or the British (or most of the Germans). The French were more extreme in their impiety than the British, if only because the Catholic Church sought to exercise a far greater hold over what they could say than the more moderate Anglican Church, or even the Church of Scotland, did in Britain. The philosophers, essayists, historians, novelists, playwrights, poetsâmost escaped any simple descriptionâwho, on any account, made up what was called loosely âthe republic of lettersâ were a very heterogeneous group. Some were clearly more radical than others, some were successful, others (often for good reasons) obscure. Some came from comfortable backgrounds, someâincluding two of the best known, Denis Diderot and Jean-Jacques Rousseauâwere the children of artisans (although prosperous, educated ones); not a few were titled aristocrats, and some were in minor orders. No group so heterogeneous could ever be expected to agree upon everything, to speak with the same voice, or even to share a common intellectual stance.
Neither can the Enlightenment easily be described as a single, coherent movement any more than any other transformative moment in history. Like the Renaissance, the Reformation and the (much-contested) Scientific Revolution that preceded it, and the Industrial Revolution and the democratic and socialist revolutions that followed, it defies simple description. It was more than a revolution in customs or a project for moderate legal and political reform, as the great Italian historian Franco Venturi argued, although it was clearly also both of these things too.22 It was more than a salon culture or even what the contemporary German philosopher JĂŒrgen Habermas has made famous as a âpublic space.â23 It was not only a new kind of book trade or an underground of racy, anti-establishment pamphleteers. All these things were, in their ways, highly significant developments in the culture of eighteenth-century Europe.24 But to argue that any one of them, or even all of them together, constituted the Enlightenment is to empty the concept of much of its real philosophical content, and without that it is hard to see that the debate over its identity can be for us, its conscious or unwilling heirs, anything more than a merely antiquarian dispute. For the Enlightenment, as its proponents insisted time and again, was above all else a âcentury of philosophy.â It is significant that Zöllner did not ask, âWhat is the Enlightenment?â He did not even ask, âWhat is an âenlightener,âââ an AufklĂ€rer, or a philosopher, which might have been another way of phrasing the same question. Instead, he asked, âWhat is enlightenment?â He was not, that is, asking about a mental state, nor about a period in social or intellectual history, nor about the objectives of an intellectual fraternity. He was asking about the content of an intellectual process.
The modern use of this phrase, âthe Enlightenment,â also suggests a discrete moment in timeâthe âlongâ eighteenth century, as it is sometimes calledâmarked off by the quite distinct intellectual concerns we associate with the nineteenth century and above all with Romanticism. Needless to say, the AufklĂ€rer themselves did not see it this way. They identified themselves and their objectives with the historical present; their concerns were with the historical future. They were conscious that they were living though a century of âlightâ or âphilosophy.â But they were also acutely aware that, as Kant famously said, although they lived in âan age of Enlightenment,â it was ânot yet an Enlightened age.â25 Kant himself did not, in fact, have a very high opinion of the present condition of humanity even within the cultivated and polite societies of Europe.
Copyright © 2013 by Anthony Pagden. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.